Skip to main content
Log in

Homology across inheritance systems

  • Published:
Biology & Philosophy Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Recent work on inheritance systems can be divided into inclusive conceptions, according to which genetic and non-genetic inheritance are both involved in the development and transmission of nearly all animal behavioral traits, and more demanding conceptions of what it takes for non-genetic resources involved in development to qualify as a distinct inheritance system. It might be thought that, if a more stringent conception is adopted, homologies could not subsist across two distinct inheritance systems. Indeed, it is commonly assumed that homology relations cannot survive a shift between genetic and cultural inheritance systems, and substantial reliance has been placed on that assumption in debates over the phylogenetic origins of hominin behavioral traits, such as male-initiated intergroup aggression. However, in the homology literature it is widely accepted that a trait can be homologous—that is, inherited continuously in two different lineages from a single common ancestor—despite divergence in the mechanisms involved in the trait’s development in the two lineages. In this paper, we argue that even on an extremely stringent understanding of what it takes for developmental resources to form a separate inheritance system, homologies can nonetheless subsist across shifts between distinct inheritance systems. We argue that this result is a merit of this way of characterizing what it is to be an inheritance system, that it has implications for adjudicating between alternative accounts of homology, and that it offers an important cautionary lesson about how (not) to reason with the homology concept, particularly in the context of cultural species.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Institutional subscriptions

Fig. 1
Fig. 2
Fig. 3
Fig. 4

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. This paper does not take a stand on the general ‘problem of homology.’ Instead, we will simply stipulate that by ‘homology’ we mean ‘taxic homology’ which we define, broadly following Wiley and Lieberman (2011), as ‘character states that are shared by two taxa and inherited continuously from their common ancestor’. In contrast, ‘homoplasy’ will refer to qualitatively similar character states that do not stem from a common ancestor (and hence diagnose polyphyletic groups). Our focus is therefore on the homology of similar character states, rather than on individuated characters whatever their state.

  2. We use the term ‘phenotype’ in the broad, ‘extended’ sense to include not only quintessential biological structures but also behaviors, mental representations, and artifacts.

  3. Animal taxa have been subject to a non-trivial amount of lateral gene exchange mediated by viral vectors (Keeling and Palmer 2008), and hybridization between disparate plant species may occur at an evolutionarily significant frequency, but these phenomena are not substantial enough to undermine the project of using DNA to build phylogenetic trees in eukaryotes.

  4. If there has been selection for mechanisms that stabilise membrane-based inheritance over and above stabilising the integrity of membranes in ontogeny, then it would qualify as a (limited) inheritance system.

  5. Some inheritance systems may have been selected to have medium fidelity of transmission, with the function of transmitting phenotypes down multiple generations, but many fewer generations than are usually involved in genetic transmission.

  6. That there is cultural heritability does not entail that there is a cultural inheritance system, on our more stringent account of the latter. A particular culturally copied phenotype can confer a fitness advantage on individuals or groups without culture being a system that is itself selected for transmitting adaptive variation down the generations.

  7. ‘Cultural assimilation’ in the sense used here is to be distinguished from the scenario wherein a trait not transmitted by any inheritance system (e.g., an individually learned trait) comes to be culturally transmitted. The process just described, which is arguably common in cultural evolution (Gers 2011), is a cultural analog of genetic assimilation, but not one that would involve the shift across inheritance systems that we contemplate in this paper. Note that if one takes a broader view of cultural assimilation such that it includes the cultural cooptation and transmission of individually learned behaviors, then the process of cultural assimilation need not begin with a genetic mutation or innovation.

  8. Further complications arise due to the fact that selection on conserved developmental mechanisms can result in the repeated origination (and loss) of a trait in a bushy clade (i.e., ‘parallelism’)—which one may (Ramsey and Peterson 2012) or may not (Currie 2013) prefer to categorize as homologs. Furthermore, one might think that behavioural traits, such as intergroup hostility, will be especially prone to iterated evolution, given that they are labile, only loosely tied to structure, and partly functionally delineated. In fact, insofar as this lability entails greater degrees of freedom in alternative character state space, the phylogenetic signal of behaviors and culturally acquired traits will be less prone to homoplastic noise (Rendall and Di Fiore 2007). In any case, these are epistemic difficulties that confront the homologization of behavioral characters in general, not simply those implicating cultural traits or shifts across inheritance systems. A full treatment of these important issues lies beyond the scope of the present discussion.

References

  • Adams D, Buchanan J (1990) The seville statement on violence. Am Psychol 45(10):1167–1168

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bertossa RC (2011) Morphology and behaviour: functional links in development and evolution. Philos Trans R Soc B 366:2056–2068

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bock K (1980) Human nature and history: A response to sociobiology. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyd R, Borgerhoff-Mulder M, Durham WH, Richerson PJ (1997) Are cultural phylogenies possible? In: Weingart P, Mitchell SD, Richerson PJ, Maasen S (eds) Human by nature. Lawrence Erlbaum, Hillsdale, pp 355–386

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon R (1990) Adaptation and environment. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan B, Collard M (2007) Investigating the peopling of North America through cladistic analyses of early paleoindian projectile points. J Anthropol Archaeol 26:366–393

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carmody RN, Wrangham RW (2009) The energetic significance of cooking. J Hum Evol 57:379–391

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Currie AM (2013) Venomous dinosaurs and rear-fanged snakes: homology and homoplasy characterized. Erkenntnis. doi:10.1007/s10670-013-9533-5

  • de Visser JA et al (2003) Evolution and detection of genetic robustness. Evolution 57(9):1959–1972

    Google Scholar 

  • De Waal F (1997) Forward to Mitchell RW, Thompson NS, Miles H (eds.), Anthropomorphism, anecdotes, and animals, SUNY Press, pp. xiii–xiv

  • Deacon TW (2003) Multilevel selection in a complex adaptive system: the problem of language origins. In: Weber B, Depew D (eds) Evolution and learning: the Baldwin effect reconsidered. MIT Press, Cambridge, pp 81–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Ehrlich PR (2000) Human natures: genes, cultures, and the human prospect. Penguin, Harmondsworth

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeland SJ, Hurst LD (1998) The genetic code is one in a million. J Mol Evol 47:238–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gers M (2011) As we build our world we build our minds: the causal role of technology in the development and evolution of human psychological traits. Doctoral Thesis, Victoria University of Wellington

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Darwinian populations and natural selection. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Godfrey-Smith P (2013) Darwinism and cultural change. Philos Trans R Soc B 367(1599):2160–2170

    Google Scholar 

  • Gottlieb G, Lickliter R (2004) The various roles of animal models in understanding human development. Soc Dev 13(2):311–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gray RD, Drummond AJ, Greenhill SJ (2009) Language phylogenies reveal expansion pulses and pauses in Pacific settlement. Science 323:479–483

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths PE (2001) Genetic information: a metaphor in search of a theory. Philos Sci 68(3):394–412

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (2003) Descent with modification: the unity underlying homology and homoplasy as seen through an analysis of development and evolution. Biol Rev 78:409–433

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hall BK (2013) ‘Homology, homoplasy, novelty, and behavior. Dev Psychobiol 55:4–12

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henrich J, Boyd R, Richerson PJ (2008) Five misunderstandings about cultural evolution. Hum Nat 19(2):119–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka E, Lamb MJ (2005) Evolution in four dimensions: genetic, epigenetic, behavioral, and symbolic variation in the history of life. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Jordan FM (2011) A phylogenetic analysis of the evolution of Austronesian sibling terminologies. Hum Biol 83(2):297–321

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keeling PJ, Palmer JD (2008) Horizontal gene transfer in eukaryotic evolution. Nat Rev Genet 9:605–618

    Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher P (1987) Précis of vaulting ambition: sociobiology and the quest for human nature. Behav Brain Sci 10:61–71

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN (2008) Exploring gene–culture interactions: insights from handedness, sexual selection and niche-construction case studies. Phil Trans R Soc B 363:3577–3589

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Laland KN, Brown G (2011) Sense and nonsense: evolutionary perspectives on human behaviour. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Lynch M, Conery JS (2000) The evolutionary fate and consequences of duplicate genes. Science 290(5494):1151–1155

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mace R, Jordan FM (2011) Macro-evolutionary studies of cultural diversity: a review of empirical studies of cultural transmission and cultural adaptation. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 366:402–411

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Machery E, Mallon R (2011) The evolution of morality. In: Doris JM (ed) Moral psychology handbook. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 3–46

    Google Scholar 

  • Maestripieri D, Roney JR (2006) Evolutionary developmental psychology: contributions from comparative research with nonhuman primates. Dev Rev 26:120–137

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Manson JH, Wrangham RW (1991) Intergroup aggression in chimpanzees and humans. Curr Anthropol 32(4):369–390

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Marks J (2002) What it means to be 98% chimpanzee: apes, people, and their genes. University of California Press, California

    Google Scholar 

  • Müller G (2003) Homology: the evolution of morphological organization. In Gerd Müller and Stuart Newman (eds.), Origination of organismal form, MIT Press, pp. 51–70

  • Oyama S (2000) The ontogeny of information: Developmental systems and evolution, Duke University Press

  • Pagel M (2009) Human language as a culturally transmitted replicator. Nat Rev Genet 10:405–415

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau D (2005) Social learning and the Baldwin effect. In: Zilhão A (ed) Evolution and rationality, and cognition. Routledge, London/New York, pp 40–60

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M (2010) Genotype–Phenotype mapping and the end of the ‘genes as blueprint’ metaphor. Phil Trans R Soc B 365:557–566

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci M, Murren CJ, Schlichting CD (2006) Phenotypic plasticity and evolution by genetic assimilation. J Exp Biol 209:2362–2367

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Powell R (2012) The future of human evolution. Br J Philos Sci 63:145–175

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prinz J (2008) Is morality innate? In Sinnott Armstrong W (ed) Moral psychology, MIT Press, Cambridge, vol 1, pp. 367-406

  • Ramsey G, Peterson A (2012) Sameness in biology. Philos Sci 79(2):255–275

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rendall D, Di Fiore A (2007) Homoplasy, homology, and the perceived special status of behavior in evolution. J Hum Evol 52(5):504–521

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richerson P, Boyd R (2005) Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Rieppel O (1992) Homology and logical fallacy. J Evol Biol 5:701–715

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Robert JS (2004) Embryology, epigenesis and evolution. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rogers DS, Feldman MS, Ehrlich PR (2009) Inferring population histories using cultural data. Proc R Soc B 276:3835–3843

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth VL (1988) The biological basis of homology. In: Humphries CJ (ed) Ontogeny and systematics. Columbia University Press, Columbia, pp 1–26

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth VL (1991) Homologies and hierarchies: problems solved and unresolved. Evol Biol 4:167–194

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roth VL (2001) Character replication. In: Wagner GP (ed) The character concept in evolutionary biology. Academic Press, London, pp 81–107

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2007) Representation in the genome and in other inheritance systems. Biol Philos 22:313–331

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2009) Imitation as an inheritance system. Phil Trans R Soc B 364:2429–2443

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea N (2013) Inherited representations are read in development. Br J Philos Sci 64(1):1–31. doi:10.1093/bjps/axr050

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea N, Pen I, Uller T (2011) Three epigenetic information channels and their different roles in evolution. J Evol Biol 24:1178–1187

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sperber D (1996) Explaining culture: a naturalistic approach. Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Sponsel LE (2010) Reflections on the possibilities of a nonkilling society and a nonkilling anthropology. In Pim JE (ed.), Nonkilling societies, creative commons, pp. 17–54

  • Sussman RW (1999) The myth of man the hunter, man the killer and the evolution of human morality. Zygon 34(3):453–471

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tehrani J, Collard M (2002) Investigating cultural evolution through biological phylogenetic analyses of Turkmen textiles. J Anthropol Archaeol 21:443–463

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tishkoff et al (2006) Convergent adaptation of human lactase persistence in Africans and Europeans. Nat Genet 39:31–40

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Valen LM (1982) Homology and Causes. J Morphol 173(3):305–312

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Vugt M (2009) Sex differences in intergroup competition, aggression, and warfare: the male warrior hypothesis. Ann NY Acad Sci 1167:124–134

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waddington C (1953) Genetic assimilation of an acquired character. Evolution 4:118–126

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (1989) The biological homology concept. Annual Rev Ecol Syst 20(1):51–69

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner GP (2007) The developmental genetics of homology. Nat Rev Genet 8:473–479

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner A (2008) Gene duplications, robustness, and evolutionary innovations. BioEssays 30:367–373

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Weiss KM, Fullerton SM (2000) Phenogenetic drift and the evolution of genotype–phenotype relationships. Theor Popul Biol 57:187–195

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • West-Eberhard MJ (2003) Developmental plasticity and evolution. Oxford University Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiley EO, Lieberman BS (2011) Phylogenetics: theory and practice of phylogenetic systematics. Wiley-Blackwell

  • Wilkins JF, Godfrey-Smith P (2009) Adaptationism and the adaptive landscape. Biol Philos 24:199–214

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wilson ML, Wrangham RW (2003) Intergroup relations in chimpanzees. Annu Rev Anthropol 32:363–392

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wrangham RW (1995) Ape culture and missing links, Symbols (2–9), Repr. In Sussman RW (1997) (ed.), The biological basis of human behavior, Simon and Schuster

  • Wrangham RW (2010) Chimpanzee violence is a serious topic, Global Nonkilling Working Papers 1:29–50

  • Wrangham RW, Peterson D (1996) Demonic males: apes and the origins of human violence. Houghton Mifflin Co, MA

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

We would like to thank Gerd Müller, Grant Ramsey, Louise Roth, Tobias Uller, Günter Wagner, and two anonymous reviewers for helpful comments on an earlier draft of this manuscript. Russell Powell would like to thank the Konrad Lorenz Institute for Evolution and Cognition Research, as well as the Templeton Foundation Grant #43160, for support of this research.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Russell Powell.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Cite this article

Powell, R., Shea, N. Homology across inheritance systems. Biol Philos 29, 781–806 (2014). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9433-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-014-9433-3

Keywords

Navigation