Skip to main content
Log in

Are there Mathematical Thought Experiments?

  • Original Paper
  • Published:
Axiomathes Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

With reference to an already existing and relatively widespread use of the expression in question, mathematical “thought experiments” (“TEs”) involve mathematical reasoning in which visualisation plays a relatively more important role. But to ensure an unambiguous and consistent use of the term, certain conditions have to be met: (1) Contrary to what has happened so far in the literature, the distinction between logical-formal thinking and experimental-operational thinking must not be ignored; (2) The separation between the context of discovery and the context of justification is to be rejected, at least in one of the main senses in which it was defended by the logical empiricists and Popper (this excludes any position which, ascribing to mathematical TEs only a heuristic role, regards them an intermediate step to attain more traditional forms of rigour); (3) The distinction between mathematical TEs and formal proofs must be regarded as one of degree, and not as a qualitative one, although this distinction may be used in a de facto way for particular or local purposes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Fig. 1

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Mach et al. 1906, pp. 197–198; Engl. Transl., p. 144. The literature in recent decades has paid little attention to TEs in mathematics and, with rare exceptions, still less to the comparison between empirical and mathematical TEs. A partial exception is the indirect, though fundamental treatment of TEs in mathematics to be found in Lakatos’s Proofs and Refutations (Lakatos 1963-4), which received relatively more attention (see for example Yuxin 1990; Koetsier 1991; Larvor 1999; Glas 2001a and Glas 2001b; Kühne 2005, pp. 356–366; Sherry 2006; Shaffer 2015; Hertogh 2021. More generally, on mathematical TEs, see above all Witt-Hansen 1976; Mueller 1969; Brown 1999, 2004, 2007, 2011, 2017, and 2021; Glas 2001a and 2001b, Van Bendegem 2003; Buzzoni 2004, 2008, 2011, 2021a and 2021b; Sherry 2006; Starikova 2007; Cohnitz 2008; Starikowa and Giaquinto 2018, Brown 2022, Norton and Parker 2022, Lenhard 2022, Fehige and Vestrucci 2022.

  2. In using the mentioned traditional distinction, however, it is important to emphasise that the expression “applied mathematics” should by no means be understood in the sense that at the beginning there would be pure mathematics, which only later applies to the real world. On the contrary, historically, mathematics first emerged as applied mathematics in the sense that it responded from the outset to demands that came from practical-operational interests. For some further details on the epistemological status of mathematics, see Buzzoni 2011.

  3. Leaving aside (for reasons of space) some differences, I would like to at least mention the broad agreement that exists between the position defended here and Peirce’s considerations on mathematics as diagrammatic reasoning. According to Peirce, in fact, the claim that, as his father Benjamin Pearce had stated, mathematics is “the science which draws necessary conclusions” (Peirce 1895, p. 7), is intimately connected with the importance of graphic or pictorial constructions, or – as Peirce expressed it – with the fact that the mathematician “observes nothing but the diagrams he constructs himself” (Peirce 1895, p. 4). As Peirce noted, in responding to the demands of experience (be they those of the engineer, the insurer, the physicist, or the businessman planning the purchase of land), the mathematician does two things: first, he tries to simplify the facts; and secondly, he tries to formulate another simpler but quite fictitious problem, which “is sufficiently like the question he should answer” to serve as a “substitute” for it. This process, which Peirce calls “skeletonization or diagrammatization of the problem”, makes possible the “tracing the consequences of the hypothesis”, which is the most characteristic aspect of mathematical work (cf. Peirce 1898, pp. 212–213; as is well known, Peirce’s reflections on diagrammatic reasoning have been often taken up in the debate of the last decades on the graphical or diagrammatic character of mathematical proofs (see e.g. Hessler and Mersch (eds.) 2009, Pombo and Gerner (eds) 2010, Panza 2012, Giardino 2013, Meynell 2018, Chapman et al (eds) 2018). In our terminology, the process of “skeletonization” or “diagrammatization” is a process of idealization subordinated to the main purpose of drawing valid consequences within an inferential symbolic space shielded from the real causal interactions present in the natural world.

  4. There is also a sense in which the neopositivist distinction between discovery and justification must be preserved, but this is not what I intend to dwell upon now. For a more detailed treatment of this point, see Buzzoni 2008, above all Ch. 1, Sects. 4–6, and Ch. 3, Sects. 4–6. For more historical details on the discovery/justification distinction, see Schickore and Steinle (eds) 2006, above all Part I and Part II.

  5. Because of this need to distinguish and at the same time connect the conceptual and the concrete-sensible aspects of imagination, the distinction drawn by Stuart 2019 between, on the one hand, imagination as an ability (imagination0), and, on the other hand, two kinds of imagination as different particular manifestations or “uses” of it (imagination1 and imagination2, to which, in my opinion, empirical research could add many more), is important. Stuart sees his distinction as qualitative (or ‘categorical’), and it is in this sense that I accept and use it here. On this point see also Savojardo 2022, who rightly insists on the connection between this distinction, the rejection of the separation between discovery and justification, and the notion of embodied cognition.

References

  • Brown JR (1997) Proofs and Pictures. Br J Philos Sci 48:161–180

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown JR (1999) Philosophy of Mathematics. An Introduction to the World of Proofs and Pictures. Routledge, New York. (quotations are from the 2008 edition)

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown JR (2004) Peeking into Plato’s Heaven. Philos Sci 71:1126–1138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown JR (2007) Thought Experiments in Science, Philosophy, and Mathematics. Croatian J Philos 7:3–27

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown JR (2011) The Laboratory of the Mind: Thought Experiments in the Natural Sciences. 2nd edition, Routledge, London

  • Brown JR (2017) Proofs and Guarantees. Math Intelligencer 39:47–50. doi https://doi.org/10.1007/s00283-017-9730-1)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown JR (2021) Rigour and Thought Experiments: Burgess and Norton. Axiomathes. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09567-2 (this issue)

  • Buzzoni M (2004) Esperimento ed esperimento mentale. Angeli, Milano

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2008) Thought Experiment in the Natural Sciences. An Operational and Reflexive-Trascendental Conception. Königshausen + Neumann, Würzburg

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2011) On Mathematical Thought Experiments. Epistemologia An Italian Journal for Philosophy of Science 34:5–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2021a) Mathematical vs Empirical Thought Experiments. In: Calosi C, Graziani P, Pietrini D, Tarozzi G (eds) Experience, Abstraction, and the Scientific Image of the World. FrancoAngeli Editore, Milan, pp 215–228

    Google Scholar 

  • Buzzoni M (2021b) A Neglected Chapter in the History of Philosophy of Mathematical Thought Experiments: Insights from Jean Piaget’s Reception of Edmond Goblot, vol 11. HOPOS, pp 282–304

  • Chapman P, Stapleton G, Moktefi A, Perez-Kriz S, Bellucci F (eds) (2018) Diagrammatic Representation and Inference.Springer, Cham

  • Cohnitz D (2008) Ørsteds ‘Gedankenexperiment’: eine Kantianische Fundierung der Infinitesimalrechnung? Ein Beitrag zur Begriffsgeschichte von ‘Gedankenexperiment’ und zur Mathematikgeschichte des frühen 19. Jahrhunderts” Kant-Studien 99:407–433

    Google Scholar 

  • Fehige Y, Vestrucci A (2022) On Thought Experiments, Theology, and Mathematical Platonism. Axiomathes, 33, n. 6 (this issue)

  • Giardino V (2013) Towards a diagrammatic classification. Knowl Eng Rev 28:237–248

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glas E (2001a) The ‘Popperian Programme’ and Mathematics. Part I: the Fallibilist Logic of Mathematical Discovery, vol 32. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, pp 119–137

  • Glas E (2001b) The ‘Popperian Programme’ and Mathematics. Part II: From Quasi-Empiricism to Mathematical Research Programmes, vol 32. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, pp 355–376

  • Goblot E (1918) Traité de logique. Colin, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinzmann G (2015) Pragmatism and the Practical Turn in Philosophy of Mathematics: Explanatory. In: Agazzi E, Heinzmann G (eds) Pragmatism and the Practical Turn in Philosophy of Sciences. Angeli, Milan, pp 113–129

    Google Scholar 

  • Heinzmann G (2022) Mathematical Understanding by Thought Experiments, this issue

  • Hempel C.G. (1965) Aspects of Scientific Explanation And Other Essays in the Philosophy of Science, Free Press, New York

  • Hertogh CP (2021) Computation and Visualization Thought Experiments after Lakatos’s Heuristic Guessing Method. Philosophical Approaches to the Foundations of Logic and Mathematics. Poznań Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, vol 114. Brill, Leiden, pp 271–297

    Google Scholar 

  • Hessler M, Mersch D (eds) (2009 (eds.)) Logik des Bildlichen. Zur Kritik der ikonischen Vernunft. Transcript, Bielefeld

  • James W (1912) Essays in Radical Empiricism. Longman, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Koetsier T (1991) Lakatos’ Philosophy of Mathematics. A Historical Approach. North Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Kühne U (2005) Die Methode des Gedankenexperiments. Suhrkamp, Frankfurt a.M

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos I (1963) -4 Proofs and Refutations. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 14: I, pp. 1–25; II, pp. 120–139, III, pp. 221–245, IV, pp. 296–342

  • Larvor B (1999) Lakatos’ Mathematical Hegelianism. The Owl of Minerva 31, pp. 23–54

  • Lenhard J (2022) Proof, Semiotics, and the Computer. On the Relevance and Limitation of Thought Experiment in Mathematics, Axiomathes, 32, n. 6 (this issue)

  • Mach E, Barth L, Engl TJ, McCormack (1906) On Thought Experiments, in: Knowledge and Error, Reidel, Dordrecht and Boston, 1976, pp. 134–147

  • Máté A (2006) Árpád Szabó and Imre Lakatos, Or the relation between history and philosophy of mathematics. Perspect Sci 14:282–301

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meynell L (2018) Images and Imagination in Thought Experiments. In: Brown JR, Fehige Y, Stuart M (eds) Kantian Accounts of Thought Experiments. Routledge, New York, pp 498–511

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill JS 1863. Utilitarianism. Parker, London

  • Miščević N (2021) Thought Experiments. Springer, Cham

    Google Scholar 

  • Mueller I (1969) Euclid’s Elements and the axiomatic method. Br J Philos Sci 20:289–309

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton J (1991) Thought Experiments in Einstein’s Work. In: Horowitz T, Massey GJ (eds) 1991, Thought Experiments in Science and Philosophy. Rowman & Littlefield, pp 129–148. Savage (MD).

  • Norton J (1996) Are Thought Experiments Just What You Thought? Can J Philos 26:333–366

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Norton JD, Parker MW (2022) An Infinite Lottery Paradox. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-021-09556-5. (this issue) Axiomathes

  • Panza M (2012) The twofold role of diagrams in Euclid’s plane geometry. Synthese 186:55–102

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce 1895 (2010) The Nature of Mathematics. Quotations are from Philosophy of Mathematics. Selected Writings, ed. by Matthew E. Moore, pp. 3–9. Indiana University Press, Bloomington and Indianapolis,

  • Peirce 1898. The Logic of Mathematics in Relation to Education.Educational Review15, pp.209–216

  • Poincaré H (1902) La Science et l’hypothèse. Paris: Flammarion. Quotations are from Science and Hypothesis. The Complete Text, Engl. Transl. by Mélanie Frappier, Smith A, Stump DJ. Bloomberg, London, 2018

  • Poincaré H(1910) The Future of Mathematics. The Monist, 20, pp. 76–92

  • Pombo O, Gerner A (eds) 2010. Studies in Diagrammatology and Diagram Praxis.College Publications, London

  • Popper KR 1969. Conjectures and Refutations, 3d ed, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London

  • Savojardo V (2022) Imaginative Resistance in Science. Foundations of Science. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10699-022-09857-x

  • Schickore J, Steinle F (eds) (2006) Revisiting discovery and justification: historical and philosophical perspectives on the context distinction. Springer, Dordrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaffer MJ (2015) Lakatos’ Quasi-empiricism in the Philosophy of Mathematics. Pol J Philos 9:71–80

    Google Scholar 

  • Sherry D (2006) Mathematical reasoning: induction, deduction and beyond. Stud Hist Philos Sci 37:489–504

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Starikova I (2007) Picture-Proofs and Platonism. Croatian J Philos 7:81–92

    Google Scholar 

  • Starikova I, Giaquinto M (2018) Thought Experiments in Mathematics. In: Brown JR, Fehige Y, Stuart M (eds) The Routledge Companion to Thought Experiments. Routledge, New York, pp 257–278

    Google Scholar 

  • Stuart MT(2019) Towards a dual process epistemology of imagination. Synthese https://doi.org/10.1007/s11229-019-02116-w

  • Szabó Á (1958) ‘Deiknymi’ [Greek δείκνυµι] als Mathematischer Terminus fur ‘Beweisen’, vol 10. Maia, N.S., pp 1–26

  • Szabò Á (1960) Anfänge des euklidischen Asiomensystems, Archive for History of Exact Sciences, 1, pp. 37–106

  • Szabò Á(1969) Anfänge der griechischen Mathematik. De Gruyter, Oldenbourg. Quotations are also from the Engl. Translation, The Beginnings of Greek Mathematics. Reidel, Dordrecht 1978

  • Van Bendegem JP (2003) Thought Experiments in Mathematics: Anything but Proof, vol 72. Philosophica, pp 9–33

  • Weyl H (1944) David Hilbert and his mathematical work. Bull Am Math Soc 50:612–654

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Witt-Hansen J Ørsted HC(1976) Immanuel Kant, und the Thought Experiment.Danish Yearbook of Philosophy, 13,48–65

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yuxin Z (1990) From the Logic of Mathematical Discovery to the Methodology of Scientific Research Programmes. Br J Philos Sci 41:377–399

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

This paper has greatly profited from conferences and discussions that took place within the FFIUM Project (Formalism, Formalization, Intuition and Understanding in Mathematics). Many thanks to Gerhard Heinzmann, the principal investigator, who made possible a research stay at the “Archives Henri Poincaré” of the Université de Nancy-Lorraine (15.1.2019-15.2.1919). Ongoing discussions with Gerhard Heinzmann led to a change in my preceding position about mathematical TEs (Buzzoni 2011). But I would like to thank also the entire research group of the FFIUM Project both for conferences held by, and for many helpful discussions with, other members of the Project. Many thanks also to Mike Stuart, who has read an earlier draft of this paper and has made many valuable suggestions for its improvement.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Marco Buzzoni.

Additional information

Publisher’s Note

Springer Nature remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

Rights and permissions

Springer Nature or its licensor holds exclusive rights to this article under a publishing agreement with the author(s) or other rightsholder(s); author self-archiving of the accepted manuscript version of this article is solely governed by the terms of such publishing agreement and applicable law.

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Buzzoni, M. Are there Mathematical Thought Experiments?. Axiomathes 32 (Suppl 1), 79–94 (2022). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-022-09641-3

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Revised:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10516-022-09641-3

Keywords

Navigation