Skip to main content

The Language of International Corporate Ethics

  • Chapter
Business Ethics: Japan and the Global Economy

Part of the book series: Issues in Business Ethics ((IBET,volume 5))

Abstract

This chapter identifies six basic languages of morals and shows that while in general it is impossible to say that one moral language is innately better, some languages are better for the purpose of characterizing international corporate responsibility. In particular, moral languages that imply minimum rather than perfectionist standards of behavior, and which are not overly dependant on analogy with human moral psychology, are better than ones ranging broadly over both the minimum and maximum standards and requiring analogy to human beings. Languages based in rights and duties, avoidance of harm, or social contracts are better for understanding international corporate ethics than ones based in virtues, self control, or the maximization of human happiness.

What we say drives what we do. If money may be said to be the basic medium of business, so language is the basic medium of ethics, and the language we use in discussing ethics in international business has dramatic implications for the health of, and quality of life within, international commerce. If we conceive international corporate responsibility in terms of “virtues” or “self-restraint” we imply a vastly different moral structure for international business ethics than if we utilize concepts of “rights” or “avoidance of harm. ”

I wish first of all to make clear that in analyzing the language of business morals I do not mean to highlight spoken languages, and the differences between, say, Japanese, French, English, and Spanish. I mean to confront something deeper, something one step removed from spoken languages, which, while related to them, concerns the fundamental structures through which we conceive ethical reality. An analogy to geometry may be helpful. The geometry that most of us learned in primary school has its roots in the teachings of the Greek geometrician, Euclid. But since the nineteenth century, other non-Euclidian geometries have arisen, usually maintaining most of the postulates of Euclid but changing critical ones. One such geometry alters Euclid’s famous “parallel” postulate, and assumes, contrary to Euclid, that parallel lines meet at infinity. English, Japanese, French, and Spanish all have ways of expressing such geometrical postulates. Each has a word for “parallel.” Each also has a way of representing “triangularity.” But the difference between the Japanese word for “triangle” and the English word for “triangle” is less significant to geometers than the difference between a Euclidian and a non-Euclidian concept of “triangle. ”

The analogy to ethics should be obvious. The deeper difference from the standpoint of international corporate ethics lies not between the English and the Japanese words for “corporate responsibility, ” but in the sets of ethical concepts we use to express “corporate responsibility. ” Just as different geometries can be used to express familiar geometric relationships, such as triangularity, different sets of ethical concepts can be used to express notions of “corporate responsibility. ” And, just as it is difficult to say that Japanese is a “better” language than English, it is difficult to say that either geometry is better in general or that one set of ethical concepts is better.

However, while in general it is impossible to say that one moral language is better, some languages may be better for some purposes. This brings me to the mission of this article. I wish to show that some moral languages are more appropriate for defining corporate responsibility. In particular, deontological or consequential ethical languages that can be used to establish minimum rather than perfectionist standards of behavior, and which are not overly dependent on analogy with human moral psychology, are better than ones ranging broadly over both minimum and maximum standards and requiring analogy to human beings. To be specific, this means that we are better off defining international standards for corporate conduct in terms of rights and duties, or avoidance of harm, or the terms of a hypothetical general consent (the social contract), than we are in terms of virtues, self-control, or the maximization of human happiness.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Preview

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

Unable to display preview. Download preview PDF.

References

  • Donaldson, T., Dunfee T.W. (1993): “Integrative Social Contracts Theory: A Communitarian Conception of Economic Ethics”, forthcoming in Economics and Philosophy. A summary of the key ideas in Integrative Social contracts Theory is provided in Chapter 3 of this book written by Thomas W. Dunfee.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, T. (1989): The Ethics of International Business, Oxford: Oxford University Press, Chapter 5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, A. (1991): “The Idea of Utilitarianism,” in Nardin, T. (ed.)(1991) Traditions of Ethics in International Affairs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, Chapter 8.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, J. (1978): “Postscript”, in Rights, Justice and the Bounds of Liberty, Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1986): Morals By Agreement, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gauthier, D. (1985): Ethics, 96, 74–88.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Institute of Moralogy (1987): An Outline of Moralogy: A New Approach to Moral Science, Tokyo: The Institute of Moralogy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kagan, S. (1989): The Limits of Morality, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, J., Ellington, J. (trans.)(1964): The Metaphysical Principles of Virtue, New York: Bobbs-Merrill, 48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I., Beck, L.W. (trans.)(1959): Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals, New York: Liberal Arts Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keeley, M. (1988): A Social Contract Theory of Organizations, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maclntyre, A.C. (1981): After Virtue: A Study in Moral Theory, Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. (1986): Faces of Hunger: An Essay on Poverty, Development and Justice, London, George Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, I. (1988): “Hunger, Needs, and Rights,” in Luper-Foy, S. (ed.); (1988): Problems of International Justice, New York: Westview Press, 63–67, 81–82.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971): A Theory of Justice, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1975): “Fairness to Goodness,” Philosophical Review, 84, 536–554.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandel, M. (1982): Liberalism and the Limits of Justice, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (1989): Sources of the Self, Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasi, J. (1989): “Individual Rights and Community Virtues,” Ethics, 101, 521–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Authors

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 1993 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Donaldson, T. (1993). The Language of International Corporate Ethics. In: Dunfee, T.W., Nagayasu, Y. (eds) Business Ethics: Japan and the Global Economy. Issues in Business Ethics, vol 5. Springer, Dordrecht. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8183-7_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-8183-7_6

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Dordrecht

  • Print ISBN: 978-90-481-4309-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-94-015-8183-7

  • eBook Packages: Springer Book Archive

Publish with us

Policies and ethics