Skip to main content

Dynamic Pragmatic View of Negation Processing

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Negation and Polarity: Experimental Perspectives

Part of the book series: Language, Cognition, and Mind ((LCAM,volume 1))

Abstract

Many psycholinguistic studies have found that processing negative sentences is difficult, and often involves the representation of the positive argument. Current rejection accounts suggest that processing the positive argument is the mandatory first step of negation processing, and the difficulty of negation comes from the extra step of embedding. We argue for a dynamic pragmatic view, suggesting that even when processing a sentence without context, comprehenders retrieve contextual information such as its Question Under Discussion (QUD), using linguistic cues. Without supporting context, negation acts as a cue for retrieving and accommodating the most prominent QUD, where the truth of the positive counterpart is at issue. QUD accommodation happens incrementally and automatically, which triggers the representation of the positive argument and contributes to the extra processing cost related to negation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Can negation triggered QUD accommodation be unified with prosodic focus triggered QUD accommodation? Hedberg and Sosa (2003) studied the intonation of negative sentences, and found that the negative morpheme or auxiliary is almost always marked with a high pitch accent, except when negation is contracted with the auxiliary “do”. Therefore, when “don’t” doesn’t receive a high pitch accent and no other constituent is focused, negation must act as a QUD cue itself. Note that in this example, if either “the door” or “open” are focused, the prominent QUD changes. For example, if “the door” is focused, the prominent QUD becomes “What isn’t open?”.

  2. 2.

    Here we restrict our attention to propositions with sentential negation. Negative imperatives (e.g. “Don’t enter this room”), negative questions (e.g. “Are you not coming to the party”), sentences with implicit negation (“It is unimportant”) or embedded negation (“It’s John who didn’t come”) should have different effects on context update. Some of these may require a context where the positive alternative is relevant (e.g. “It is unimportant” > whether it is important is relevant; “Don’t enter this room” > the outcome of entering this room is relevant).

  3. 3.

    Note that in natural language use, a simple negative sentence like “x is not y” can have other QUDs, depending on the constituent in focus, such as “which is not y”, or “x is not what?”. We argue that without context, participants accommodate the most likely QUD for this construction, which is “whether x is y”.

  4. 4.

    To control for the potential typicality effects of the images, we ran a follow-up study using the same items, but replaced all the negative sentences with affirmative ones (fillers are adjusted accordingly to balance polarity and clefting). The results show no significant interaction between match and clefting, nor any main effect of clefting. Instead, match images have faster response to mismatch images. Thus we conclude that there is no inherent difficulty in recognizing either type of image.

  5. 5.

    Here we assume verification is easier than falsification. However the reason is unclear. In fact, we found that in an overt string comparison task, identifying a match is not in general easier than identifying a mismatch (Tian 2014). However, in a sentence-picture verification task, it could be that when sentences are processed first, the representation of the sentence primes the image that makes the sentence true. When pictures are processed first, it facilitates the processing of a true sentence also by priming its representation.

  6. 6.

    Drawing this inference also requires learning and expecting both mentioned items to be in the display, and that one is positioned above the other. This information tended to be giving in the instructions in previous studies, and participants were exposed to pictures like this in practice. However, it is likely that drawing an inference for sentences containing such “context-dependent” binary predicates is more difficult than for sentences with natural binary predicates, such as “The door isn’t open”.

References

  • Altmann, G., & Kamide, Y. (1999). Incremental interpretation at verbs: Restricting the domain of subsequent reference. Cognition, 73(3), 247–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Altmann, G., & Kamide, Y. (2007). The real-time mediation of visual attention by language and world knowledge: Linking anticipatory (and other) eye movements to linguistic processing. Journal of Memory and Language, 57(4), 502–518.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Altmann, G., & Kamide, Y. (2009). Discourse-mediation of the mapping between language and the visual world: Eye movements and mental representation. Cognition, 111(1), 55–71.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Arroyo, F. (1982). Negatives in context. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 21(1), 118–126.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barr, D. J. (2008). Pragmatic expectations and linguistic evidence: Listeners anticipate but do not integrate common ground. Cognition, 109(1), 18–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barsalou, L. W. (1999). Perceptual symbol systems. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 22(04), 577–660.

    Google Scholar 

  • Breheny, R., Ferguson, H. J., & Katsos, N. (2013). Taking the epistemic step: Toward a model of on-line access to conversational implicatures. Cognition, 126(3), 423–440.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brown-Schmidt, S., Gunlogson, C., & Tanenhaus, M. (2008). Addressees distinguish shared from private information when interpreting questions during interactive conversation. Cognition, 107(3), 1122–1134.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carlson, L. (1983). Dialogue games: An approach to discourse analysis. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carpenter, P. A., & Just, M. A. (1975). Sentence comprehension: A psycholinguistic processing model of verification. Psychological Review, 82(1), 45–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. H. (1976). Semantics and comprehension. The Hague: Mouton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clark, H. H., & Chase, W. G. (1972). On the process of comparing sentences against pictures. Cognitive Psychology, 3(3), 472–517.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. (1974). The control of eye fixation by the meaning of spoken language: A new methodology for the real-time investigation of speech perception, memory, and language processing. Cognitive Psychology, 6, 84–107.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornish, E., & Wason, P. (1970). The recall of affirmative and negative sentences in an incidental learning task. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 22(2), 109–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dale, R., & Duran, N. D. (2011). The cognitive dynamics of negated sentence verification. Cognitive Science, 35(5), 983–996.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Evans, J. S. B. T., Clibbens, J., & Rood, B. (1996). The role of implicit and explicit negation in conditional reasoning bias. Journal of Memory and Language, 35(3), 392–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischler, I., Bloom, P. A., Childers, D. G., Roucos, S. E., & Perry, N. W. (1983). Brain potentials related to stages of sentence verification. Psychophysiology, 20(4), 400–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginzburg, J. (2012). The interactive stance: Meaning for conversation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giora, R. (2006). Anything negatives can do affirmatives can do just as well, except for some metaphors. Journal of Pragmatics, 38(7), 981–1014.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Giora, R. (2016, this volume). When negatives are easier to understand than affirmatives: The case of negative sarcasm. In P. Larrivée & C. Lee (Eds.), Negation and polarity: Experimental perspectives (pp. 127–143). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. M. (1997). What memory is for: Creating meaning in the service of action. Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 20(1), 41–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Glenberg, A. M., Robertson, D. A., Jansen, J. L., & Johnson-Glenberg, M. C. (1999). Not propositions. Cognitive Systems Research, 1(1), 19–33.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gough, P. (1965). Grammatical transformations and speed of understanding. Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal Behavior, 4(2), 107–111.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grice, H. (1975). Logic and conversation. In R. Stainton (Ed.), Perspectives in the philosophy of language (pp. 41–58). Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hasson, U., & Glucksberg, S. (2006). Does understanding negation entail affirmation? An examination of negated metaphors. Journal of Pragmatics, 38(7), 1015–1032.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hedberg, N., & Sosa, J. (2003). Pitch contours in negative sentences. Poster presented at the 15th International Congress of Phonetic Sciences, Barcelona.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hindy, N. C., Solomon, S. H., Altmann, G. T. M., & Thompson-Schill, S. L. (2013). A cortical network for the encoding of object change. Cerebral Cortex, bht275.

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn, L. R. (1978). Lexical incorporation, implicature, and the least effort hypothesis. CLS, 14, 196–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huettig, F., Rommers, J., & Meyer, A. S. (2011). Using the visual world paradigm to study language processing: A review and critical evaluation. Acta Psychologica, 137(2), 151–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karttunen, L. (1974). Presupposition and linguistic context. Theoretical Linguistics, 1(1), 181–194.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaup, B., Yaxley, R. H., Madden, C. J., Zwaan, R., & Lüdtke, J. (2007a). Experiential simulations of negated text information. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 60, 976–990.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaup, B., Zwaan, R., & Lüdtke, J. (2005). Effects of negation, truth value, and delay on picture recognition after reading affirmative and negative sentences. In B. G. Bara et al. (Eds.), Proceedings of the 27th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1114–1119). Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kaup, B., Zwaan, R., & Lüdtke, J. (2006). Procesing negated sentences with contradictory predicates: Is a door that is not open mentally closed? Journal of Pragmatics, 38, 1033–1050.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaup, B., Zwaan, R., & Lüdtke, J. (2007b). The experiential view of language comprehension: How is negated text information represented? In F. Schmalhofer & C. A. Perfetti (Eds.), Higher level language processes in the brain: Inference and comprehension processes (pp. 255–288). Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lee, C. (2016, this volume). Metalinguistically negated versus descriptively negated adverbials: ERP and other evidence. In P. Larrivée & C. Lee (Eds.), Negation and polarity: Experimental perspectives (pp. 229–255). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levinson, S. C. (1983). Pragmatics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1979). Scorekeeping in a language game. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 8(1), 339–359.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lüdtke, J., Friedrich, C. K., De Filippis, M., & Kaup, B. (2008). Event-related potential correlates of negation in a sentence-picture verification paradigm. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20(8), 1355–1370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lüdtke, J., & Kaup, B. (2006). Context effects when reading negative and affirmative sentences. In R. Sun & N. Miyake (Eds.), Proceedings of the 28th Annual Conference of the Cognitive Science Society (pp. 1735–1740). Mahwah: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mckinstry, C., Dale, R., & Spivey, M. J. (2008). Action dynamics reveal parallel competition in decision making. Psychological Science, 19(1), 22–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nieuwland, M. S., & Kuperberg, G. R. (2008). When the truth is not too hard to handle: an event-related potential study on the pragmatics of negation. Psychological Science: A Journal of the American Psychological Society/APS, 19(12), 1213–1218.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Oaksford, M., & Stenning, K. (1992). Reasoning with conditionals containing negated constituents. Journal of Experimental Psychology. Learning, Memory, and Cognition, 18(4), 835.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Prado, J., & Noveck, I. A. (2006). How reaction time measures elucidate the matching bias and the way negations are processed. Thinking & Reasoning, 12(3), 309–328.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, C. (2012). Information structure in discourse: Towards an integrated formal theory of pragmatics. Semantics and Pragmatics, 5(6), 1–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. (1948). Human knowledge: Its scope and limits. New York: Simon & Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1973). Presuppositions. Journal of Philosophical Logic, 2, 447–457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1978). Assertion. In P. Cole (Ed.), Syntax and semantics (pp. 315–332). New York: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. (1998). On the representation of context. Journal of Logic, Language and Information, 7, 3–19.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tanenhaus, M. K., Carroll, J., & Bever, T. (1976). Sentence-picture verification models as theories of sentence comprehension: A critique of Carpenter and Just. Psychological Review, 83(4), 310–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tanenhaus, M. K., Spivey-Knowlton, M., Eberhard, K., & Sedivy, J. (1995). Integration of visual and linguistic information in spoken language comprehension. Science, 268(5217), 1632–1634.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tettamanti, M., Manenti, R., Della Rosa, P. A., Falini, A., Perani, D., Cappa, S. F., & Moro, A. (2008). Negation in the brain: Modulating action representations. Neuroimage, 43(2), 358–367.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tian, Y. (2014). Negation processing: A dynamic pragmatic account. Ph.D. dissertation, University College London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tian, Y., & Breheny, R. (Under review). A new look at negative sentence verification.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tian, Y., Breheny, R., & Ferguson, H. (2010). Why we simulate negated information: A dynamic pragmatic account. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 63(12), 2305–2312.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tian, Y., Ferguson, H., & Breheny, R. (Under review). Processing negation without context—Why and when we represent the positive counterpart.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasino, B., Weiss, P. H., & Fink, G. R. (2010). To move or not to move: imperatives modulate action-related verb processing in the motor system. Neuroscience, 169(1), 246–258.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tottie, G. (1991). Negation in English speech and writing: A study in variation. San Diego: Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trabasso, T., & Rollins, H. (1971). Storage and verification stages in processing concepts. Cognitive Psychology, 2(3), 239–289.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van Berkum, J., van den Brink, D., Tesink, C. M. J. Y., Kos, M., & Hagoort, P. (2008). The neural integration of speaker and message. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience, 20(4), 580–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Van der Sandt, R. (1988). Context and presupposition. London: Croom Helm.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (2004). Would you believe it? The king of France is back! Presuppositions and truth-value intuitions. In M. Reimer & A. Bezuidenhout (Eds.), Descriptions and beyond (pp. 315–341). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Fintel, K. (2008). What is presupposition accommodation, again? Philosophical Perspectives, 22(1), 137–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wales, R. J., & Grieve, R. (1969). What is so difficult about negation? Perception and Psychophysics, 6(6), 327–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wallage, P. (2016, this volume). Identifying the role of pragmatic activation in the changes to the expression of English negation. In P. Larrivée & C. Lee (Eds.), Negation and polarity: Experimental perspectives (pp. 199–227). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. (1961). Response to affirmative and negative binary statements. British Journal of Psychology, 52, 133–142.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wason, P. (1965). The contexts of plausible denial. Journal of Verbal Learning Verbal Behavior, 4(1), 7–11.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, R., & Chase, W. G. (1971). Additive stages in the comparison of sentences and pictures. Paper presented at the Midwestern Psychological Association meetings, Chicago.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwaan, R. (2004). The immersed experiencer: Toward an embodied theory of language comprehension. Psychology of Learning and Motivation, 44, 35–62.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Ye Tian .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tian, Y., Breheny, R. (2016). Dynamic Pragmatic View of Negation Processing. In: Larrivée, P., Lee, C. (eds) Negation and Polarity: Experimental Perspectives. Language, Cognition, and Mind, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-17464-8_2

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-17464-8_2

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-17463-1

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-17464-8

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics