Skip to main content
Log in

The Propensity Interpretation of Probability: A Re-evaluation

  • Original Article
  • Published:
Erkenntnis Aims and scope Submit manuscript

Abstract

Single-case and long-run propensity theories are among the main objective interpretations of probability. There have been various objections to these theories, e.g. that it is difficult to explain why propensities should satisfy the probability axioms and, worse, that propensities are at odds with these axioms, that the explication of propensities is circular and accordingly not informative, and that single-case propensities are metaphysical and accordingly non-scientific. We consider various propensity theories of probability and their prospects in light of these objections. We argue that while propensity theories face challenges, these challenges do not undermine their validity as prospective interpretations of probability in science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this article

Price excludes VAT (USA)
Tax calculation will be finalised during checkout.

Instant access to the full article PDF.

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. Poincaré (1902/1952), p. 186.

  2. That is not to say that the interpretation of probability cannot change the broadly accepted calculus of probability. In this paper, we shall focus on concepts of probability that satisfy the probability calculus.

  3. Here and henceforth by ‘frequency’ we mean relative frequency.

  4. Three comments: (1) Long-run propensity theories have also been attributed, retroactively, to Cramer (1946) and Braithwaite (1953) (Mellor 1971, p. 66, Levi 1973, p. 525, Kyburg 1974, p. 358). (2) Both Hacking’s and Levi’s theories rely on Braithwaite’s (1953) ideas about how to define frequency in the long-run, and accordingly they share various aspects. Levi (1967, p. 192) describes his view as a “qualified propensity interpretation.” But, later on, he (1977, endnotes 13 and 15, pp. 453–454) objects to the view that he and Hacking are propensity theorists. He (ibid., p. 446) emphasizes that in describing his view as a qualified propensity interpretation he “wished to treat chance predicates as primitives and to refuse to offer a semantics for chance predicates in terms of test behavior.” And although he “meant to suggest a certain analogy between chance predicates and disposition predicates in that both sorts of predicates should be taken as primitive, [he] meant to deny that reduction sentences could serve to illuminate the connections between chance and test behavior in the way they can illuminate the connections between disposition and test behavior.” (3) Gillies (2000a, p. 209) notes that he conceived his (1973) theory as an objective, non-frequency theory of probability that is not a propensity theory, partly because it differed from Popper’s theory. But in the meantime the term propensity “has taken on the broader meaning of an objective but non-frequency view of probability” and accordingly he would now classify his earlier position as “one particular example of a propensity theory.”

  5. The distinction between tendency and dispositional propensity theories is inspired by Mellor’s (1971, pp. 68–70). Mellor maintains that propensities are dispositions, and he criticizes the tendency interpretation of propensities as either viciously circular or inadequate.

  6. In Sect. 5.3.6, we shall discuss Fetzer’s response to Humphreys’ paradox.

  7. For a critical review of propensity theories of probability up to the early 1970s see Kyburg (1974), and for a recent critical discussion of propensity theories see Eagle (2004).

  8. Two comments: (1) For ease of presentation, we shall sometimes say that the conditioning events determine the propensity of the conditioned event, leaving open the nature of the determination. (2) In theories in which propensities are not probabilities, the above conditional probability will denote the probability distribution that is the display of the propensity, and the conditioning events will denote the conditions that display the propensity.

  9. For a critique of Popper’s interpretation of QM, see Bub (1975) and Bub and Pitowsky (1985).

  10. Hacking (1965, pp. 13, 25) notes that “von Mises’ probability is a property of a series, but it is intended as a model of a property of what [von Mises] calls an experimental set-up.” Hacking says that he “copied the very word ‘set-up’ from [von Mises’] English translators” and followed “Venn and von Mises, intending to explain frequency in the long run by means of chance set-ups.” And Gillies (2000b, p. 811) remarks that Popper’s suggestion that probabilities should be related to repeatable conditions rather than collectives had already been made by Kolmogorov (1933/1950, pp. 3–4).

  11. Popper (1959a, p. 29).

  12. For objections to finite long-run frequency theories of probability along these lines, see Hájek (1997, pp. 209–210) and (2012, Sect. 3.4) and Gillies (2000a, pp. 125, 137–40).

  13. For want of space, we cannot discuss the application of Hacking’s theory to statistical inference.

  14. Hacking borrows the following theses from Koopman’s logic: (I) Implication: If \( h \) implies \( i \), then \( h/e\,\; \le \;\;i/e \); (II) Conjunction: If \( e \) implies \( i \), then \( h/e\,\; \le \;\;i/e \); (III) Transitivity: If \( h/e\;\; \le \;\;i/d \) and \( i/d\;\; \le \;\;j/c \), then \( h/e\;\; \le \;\;j/c \); (IV) Identity: \( h/e\,\le\, i/i \); where here ‘implies’ means logically implies and ‘\(h/e\,\le\, i/e \)’ means \( e \) supports \( i \) at least as well as it supports \( h \).

  15. For a critical discussion of the Principle of Irrelevance, see Seidenfeld (1978, 1979).

  16. Hacking also proposes a generalization of the principle (under certain conditions) to cases in which the knowledge is that the chance of \( E \) is one of a set of possible chances.

  17. For examples of such models, see Keller (1986) and Diaconis et al. (2007).

  18. SCIKT stands for ‘same-causal-influences kind of trial’ or ‘same-causal-influences kinds of trials’, and DCIKT stands for ‘different-causal-influences kind of trial’ or ‘different-causal-influences kinds of trials’. Context will determine whether each of these acronyms refers to a kind of trial or kinds of trials.

  19. See, for example, Bohm (1952), Bell (1982), Dürr et al. (1992), Bohm and Hiley (1993) and Goldstein (2013).

  20. It is important to note that due to the uncertainty principle, experimenters cannot realize such a SCIKT at will.

  21. Let \( Q_{t} (X_{t} ,Y_{t} ) \) be the actual position configuration of the universe at a certain time \( t \), where \( X \) is a subsystem of the universe (e.g. the particle and the measurement apparatus) and \( Y \) is its actual environment (i.e. the rest of the universe). Dürr, Goldstein and Zanghì call \( \psi_{t} (x) = \varPsi_{t} (x,Y_{t} ) \) the conditional wavefunction of \( X \); where \( \varPsi \) is the wavefunction of the universe, and \( x \) is a variable ranging over the possible position configurations of \( X .\)

    Conditional wavefunctions do not generally evolve according to the Schrödinger equation. However, when certain conditions are met—when the subsystem and the environment do not interact or, more generally, when the universal wavefunction evolves into a wide separation of components in the configuration space of the entire system—a conditional wavefunction will evolve according to the Schrödinger equation. When this is the case, the conditional wavefunction becomes the effective wavefunction.

  22. As Gillies (ibid., p. 92) notes, the title of this law was suggested by Keynes (1921, p. 336).

  23. Here we followed von Mises’ terminology. Gillies calls this principle the Law of Excluded Gambling Systems.

  24. The claim that von Mises’ philosophy of probability is operationalist is questionable, as the infinite frequencies that explicate probabilities in von Mises’ theory are not observable.

  25. Recall that (INT) applies only for sufficiently long sequences, where a binomial distribution approximates a normal distribution.

  26. To simplify notation, we suppress the spacing condition in \( S \).

  27. \( H_{1} \) and \( H_{2} \) are not joint propositions, but they can easily be converted to such propositions by adding to each of them the proposition that the outcome of our trial is a 0.3 frequency of heads.

  28. Obviously, such data will also falsify \( H_{2} \).

  29. In analyzing Popper’s (1957, 1959a) propensity theory, Rosenthal (2006, pp. 106–107) argues against the idea embodied in the Frequency Postulate that “it presupposes a non-probabilistic connection between probabilities and relative frequencies, which definitely does not exist.” Rosenthal points out that if propensity is characterized as a disposition to produce certain frequencies in the long run, then it is a disposition that is only probabilistically connected to its manifestations, and accordingly we face a circularity: “the concept of probability that should be explicated via the idea of propensity is in fact presupposed by it”.

  30. More precisely, to break even the monetary value of \( \delta S \) should be sufficiently small so as to stop any transfer of money.

  31. See, for example, de Finetti (1974a, Chap. 2) and Levi (1989).

  32. Similarly, Rosenthal (2006, p. 107) argues that if we think about the single-case propensity of an event \( A \) as an indeterministic disposition of a set-up \( S \) to produce \( A \), as some of Popper’s early writings on propensity suggest, the analysis of single-case propensity will be circular. Dispositions are characterized through their manifestations: the propensity of \( S \) to produce \( A \) is displayed just in case \( A \) actually occurs upon the realization of \( S \). But since \( A \) occurs only with a certain probability \( p \), the disposition of \( S \) to produce \( A \) is displayed only with a certain probability. Thus, the very concept of probability that is supposed to be interpreted by the concept of single-case propensity is presupposed.

  33. Miller actually does not support a single-case propensity theory, though he provides a sympathetic interpretation of what he considers as the “most interesting and fertile strain” of Popper’s “numerous expositions of the propensity interpretation” (Miller 1994, p. 175).

  34. For such an account of theoretical terms, see Lewis (1970).

  35. Mellor (2005) does not talk about the implication of the failure of Necessity for causation, but it is clear from his (1995, Chap. 4) that this failure entails a gap between deterministic and indeterministic causation.

  36. Mellor calls these possibilities metaphysical to distinguish them from epistemic possibilities that reflect knowledge and ignorance.

  37. Two comments: (1) Humphreys (2004, p. 669) notes that “CI stands for conditional independence, not causal independence.” (2) Humphreys (ibid.) proposes two other variants of this argument. In Sect. 5.2, footnote 40, we argue that our proposed resolution also applies to the other versions of the argument.

  38. In fact, things are a bit more complicated. First, some interpretations of QM postulate the existence of backward causation (for a discussion of such interpretations and the challenges they encounter, see Berkovitz 2008 and 2011 and references therein). If such causal influences existed, there might not be an initial state of the universe in the conventional sense of influencing but not being influenced by other states. Yet, even in universes in which backward causation exists, there might be events in the probability space that have no conditions to determine their propensities. Second, it may be suggested that if an initial state of the universe existed, some laws of nature could determine its propensity. It is noteworthy, however, that none of our current or previous scientific theories provides such a propensity, and there seems to be no reason to think that future theories will be different.

  39. For more about de Finetti’s non-standard concept of conditional probability, see Sect. 7.3 and Berkovitz (2012a).

  40. Humphreys (2004) proposes two other versions of his paradox. Each of these versions replaces CI by another principle. One version is based on the zero influence principle, which states that when \( t_{2} < t_{3} \),\( Pr_{{B_{{t_{1} }} }} (I_{{t_{2} }} /T_{{t_{3} }} ) = 0 \). The other version is based on the fixity principle, which states that when \( t_{2} < t_{3} \),\( Pr_{{B_{{t_{1} }} }} (I_{{t_{2} }} /T_{{t_{3} }} ) = 0\;\text{or}\;1 \). Like CI, both of these principles violate the symmetry between conditioned and conditioning events in standard conditional probability and accordingly they do not obtain in the above representation of propensity.

  41. Humphreys (2004, pp. 671–672) characterizes the co-production interpretation for time-dependent propensities. “A co-production interpretation considers the conditional propensity to be located in structural conditions present at an initial time \( t \), with \( Pr_{t} ( \cdot / \cdot ) \) being a propensity at \( t \) to produce the events which serve as the two arguments of the conditional propensity…. The key feature of co-productions interpretations is that the representations of the conditions present at the initial time \( t \) are not included in the algebra or σ-algebra of events within the probability space.” But this characterization could be easily translated to time-independent propensities.

  42. The suggestion here is that such conditionals may represent causal dispositions, not that they provide a reductive analysis of causation. In Lewis’s (1986, pp. 175–184) influential account of indeterministic causation, causation is explicated in terms of counterfactuals with probabilistic consequent. Although the above conditionals are substantially different, arguably they could express causal dispositions or tendencies.

  43. McCurdy argues that CI fails because the conditioned and conditioning events in CI are effects of a common cause and accordingly they are not probabilistically independent of each other. Humphreys (2004, Sect. 6) replies that although a plausible case can be made for McCurdy’s co-production interpretation in the photon example discussed above, a formally identical example demonstrates that McCurdy’s attempt to resolve Humphreys’ paradox fails. Humphreys suggests the following example. A spherical radiation detector surrounds a radioactive source of alpha particles. The detector, which is shielded from other sources, is not perfectly reliable so that not all emitted particles are detected. The emission of an alpha particle in a specified time period is assumed to be an indeterministic process, as the case is in the orthodox and various other interpretations of QM. Let \( Pr_{{t_{0} }} (E_{{t_{1} }} /D_{{t_{2} }} \& B_{{t_{0} }} ) \) be the propensity at time \( t_{0} \) for an alpha particle to be emitted during a short time interval \( t_{I} \) conditional upon the alpha particle being detected at \( t_{2} \); where \( t_{0} < t_{1} < t_{2} \) and \( B_{{t_{0} }} \) are the ‘background conditions’ that include all the features that affect the propensity value at \( t_{0} \). Humphreys (ibid., p. 675) believes that in this example CI – \( Pr_{{t_{0} }} (E_{{t_{1} }} /D_{{t_{2} }} \& B_{{t_{0} }} ) = Pr_{{t_{0} }} (E_{{t_{1} }} /B_{{t_{0} }} ) \)—is evidently true and accordingly his challenge still stands. But in McCurdy’s account of propensity, CI fails; for it follows from the probability calculus that if \( Pr_{{t_{0} }} (D_{{t_{2} }} /E_{{t_{1} }} \& B_{{t_{0} }} ) \ne Pr_{{t_{0} }} (D_{{t_{2} }} /B_{{t_{0} }} ) \), then \( Pr_{{t_{0} }} (E_{{t_{1} }} /D_{{t_{2} }} \& B_{{t_{0} }} ) \ne Pr_{{t_{0} }} (E_{{t_{1} }} /B_{{t_{0} }} ) \). While Humphreys is right to object to McCurdy’s reasoning against CI on the basis of the existence of a common cause, the objection to CI need not rely on such reasoning: it could simply be based on the symmetry of standard conditional probability.

  44. For continuity with the notation of previous sections, here and henceforth in this section we substitute ‘\( A \)’ for ‘\( a \)’ and ‘\( E \)’ for ‘\( b \)’ in the quotations.

  45. For a similar criticism, see Drouet (2011), pp. 158–159.

  46. De Finetti (1974a, Chap. 4, 1974b, pp. 307–310) characterizes subjective conditional probabilities as the probabilities of conditional events. But in his case, conditional events and their probabilities are not mysterious. One may plausibly interpret conditional events as three-valued statements and probabilities of conditional events as conditionals with probabilistic consequences (see Sect. 7.3 and Berkovitz 2012a).

  47. There are also other attempts to address Humphreys’ paradox, such as Albert (2007) and Belnap (2007), which for lack of space we cannot discuss here.

  48. The same reasoning may apply to other scientific disciplines that are highly mathematical. For example, in modern economics mathematics constitutes fundamental features of the economic realm.

  49. For a recent review of and commentary on Zeno’s paradoxes, see Huggett (1999, 2010) and references therein.

  50. There are different ways to define independent trials. A trial may be said to be independent of other trials if and only if the probability of its occurrence is independent of the occurrence of the other trials. On this definition, we need to add a qualification to the weak law of large numbers: if the propensity of E in a trial of kind T is p, then the frequency of E in a long series of unbiased independent trials of kind T will almost certainly be equal to \( p \). A series of independent trials of a certain kind may be biased because of backward causation, e.g. when the outcome of a trial of that kind is a partial cause of the trial’s occurrence. In such a series, trials could be causally and accordingly probabilistically independent. Yet, due to backward causation, the series will be biased, so that there will be a low probability that the long-run frequency of the outcomes of trials will reflect the probability of the outcome in any individual trial. Berkovitz (2008, 2011) argues that such scenarios are expected in retro-causal interpretations of quantum mechanics, where closed causal loops occur due to backward causation. Another way to define independent trials is in terms of the outcomes of trials: a series of trials is independent if and only if the probability of the joint outcome of the series factorizes into the probabilities of the individual outcomes. On this definition, the weak law of large numbers does not require any modification. For an example of such a concept of independence, see Hacking’s definition of independent trials in Sect. 3.2.2.

  51. Lewis uses the term ‘credence’, but his concept of credence is akin to subjective probability.

  52. This is a consequence of Lewis’ reformulation of the Principal Principle.

  53. The mathematical expression of the weak law of large numbers is the following. Let \( P_{C} (E) \) be the probability of \( E \) in conditions \( C \) and \( f_{{C^{n} }} (E) \) be the frequency of \( E \) in a series of \( n \) independent repetitions of \( C \), where \( C^{n} \) denotes such a series. Then, for any \( \varepsilon > 0 \), \( \lim_{n \to \infty } (\left| {P(f_{{C^{n} }} (E)) - P_{C} (E)} \right| < \varepsilon ) = 1 \).

  54. See, for example, Hacking (1965, pp. 5–7) and Howson and Ubach (1993, pp. 344–347).

  55. Similarly, in consistent infinite long-run propensity theories the relation between propensities and (infinite) frequencies is indirect: it is expressed in probabilistic terms. For example, let the infinite long-run propensity of an event \( E \) in conditions \( C \) be \( p \). The propensity that the frequency of \( E \) in an infinite series of independent repetitions of \( C \) will be \( p \), is 1. But there exist infinitely many possible series in which the frequency of \( E \) deviates substantially (extremely) from \( p \).

References

  • Abrams, M. (2015). Evolutionary statisticalism: The missed interpretation. Erkenntnis (submitted).

  • Adams, R. (1974). Theories of actuality. Noûs, 8(3), 211–231. Reprinted in Loux 1979, pp. 190–209.

  • Albert, M. (2007). The propensity theory: A decision-theoretic restatement. Synthese, 156(3), 587–603.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. Metaphysics, Book 1. (W. D. Ross, Trans.) http://classics.mit.edu/Aristotle/metaphysics.1.i.html

  • Bell, J. (1982). On the impossible pilot wave. Foundations of Physics, 12(10), 989–999. Reprinted in Bell, J. (1987). Speakable and unspeakable in quantum mechanics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 159–168.

  • Belnap, N. (2007). Propensities and probabilities. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38(3), 593–625.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bergson, H. (1889/1910). Time and free will: An essay on the immediate data of consciousness. (F. L. Pogson, Trans.) London: George Allen & Unwin.

  • Berkovitz, J. (2008). On predictions in retro-causal interpretations of quantum mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 39(4), 709–735.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J. (2011). On explanation in retro-causal interpretations of quantum mechanics. In M. Suárez (Ed.), Probabilities, causes, and propensities in physics (pp. 115–155). Synthese Library, New York: Springer.

  • Berkovitz, J. (2012a). The world according to de Finetti: On de Finetti’s theory of probability and its application to quantum mechanics’. In Y. Ben Menachem & M. Hemmo (Eds.), Probability in physics (pp. 249–280). New York: Springer, The Frontiers Collection.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Berkovitz, J. (2012b). On mathematical explanations of physical facts. In The Paper was presented at the Mathematical and Geometrical Explanations in Physics workshop, Autonomous University of Barcelona, 9–10 March, 2012.

  • Bohm, D. (1952). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of ‘hidden’ variables, I and II. Physical Review, 85(2), 166–193.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bohm, D., & Hiley, B. J. (1993). The undivided universe: An ontological interpretation of quantum theory. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Braithwaite, R. B. (1953). Scientific explanation: A study of the function of theory, probability and law in science. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

  • Bub, J. (1975). Popper’s propensity interpretation of probability and quantum mechanics. In Maxwell and Anderson (1975), pp. 416–429.

  • Bub, J., & Pitowsky, I. (1985). Critical Notice of Karl Popper’s Postscript to the logic of scientific discovery. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 15(3), 539–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bueno, O., & Colyvan, M. (2011). An inferential conception of the application of mathematics. Nous, 45(2), 345–374.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (2007). The emergence and interpretation of probability in Bohmian mechanics. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 38(2), 351–370.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1952). The continuum of inductive methods. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cassirer, E. (1907). Kant und die moderne Mathematik. Kant-Studien, 12, 1–49.

  • Cramer, H. (1946). Mathematical Methods of Statistics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

  • De Finetti, B. (1972). Probability, induction and statistics. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1974a). Theory of probability (Vol. 1). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, B. (1974b). Theory of probability (Vol. 2). New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diaconis, P., Holmes, S., & Montgomery, R. (2007). Dynmaical bias in the coin toss. SIAM Review, 49(2), 211–235.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drouet, I. (2011). Propensities and conditional probabilities. International Journal of Approximate Reasoning, 52(2), 153–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drouet, I., & Merlin, F. (2014). The propensity interpretation of fitness and the propensity interpretation of probability. Erkenntnis (this volume).

  • Dürr, D., Goldstein, S., & Zanghì, N. (1992). Quantum equilibrium and the origin of absolute uncertainty. Journal of Statistical Physics, 67(5–6), 843–907.

  • Eagle, A. (2004). Twenty-one arguments against propensity analyses of probability. Erkenntnis, 60(3), 371–416.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, J. H. (1974). A single case propensity theory of explanation. Synthese, 28(2), 171–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, J. H. (1981). Scientific knowledge: Causality, explanation and corroboration. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fetzer, J. H. (1982). Probabilistic explanations. In P. Asquith & T. N. Nickles (Eds.), PSA (Vol. 2, pp. 194–207). East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association.

  • French, S., & Ladyman, J. (1999). Reinflating the semantic approach. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13(2), 103–121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (2000). A parting of the ways: Carnap. Cassirer and Heidegger, Chicago and La Salle, Illinois: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Galilei, G. (1623/1960). The Assayer. In The Controversy of the Comets of 1618 (S. Drake, Trans.). Philadelphia: The University of Pennsylvania Press.

  • Giere, R. (1973a). Review of Mellor’s The Matter of Chance. Ratio, 15, 149–155.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1973b). Objective single-case probabilities and the foundations of statistics. In P. Suppes, et al. (Eds.), Logic, methodology and philosophy of science (Vol. IV, pp. 467–483). Amsterdam, London: North-Holland Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. (1975). The epistemological roots of scientific knowledge. In Maxwell and Anderson (1975), pp. 212- 261.

  • Giere, R. (1979). Propensity and necessity. Synthese, 40(3), 439–451.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (1973). An objective theory of probability. London: Methuen & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (2000a). Philosophical theories of probability. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gillies, D. (2000b). Varieties of propensities. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 51(4), 807–835.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldstein, S. (2013). Bohmian mechanics. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/qm-bohm/

  • Hacking, I. (1965). Logic of statistical inference. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (1997). “Mises Redux”—Redux: Fifteen arguments against finite frequentism. Erkenntnis, 45(2/3), 209–227.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2003). What conditional probability could not be? Synthese, 137(3), 273–323.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hájek, A. (2012). Interpretations of probability. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2012 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2012/entries/probability-interpret/

  • Heidegger, M. (1927/1962). Being and Time (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  • Hemmo, M., & Shenker, O. (2014). Probability and typicality in deterministic physics. Erkenntnis (this volume).

  • Howson, C., & Urbach, P. (1993). Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach (2nd ed.). Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. (1999). Space from Zeno to Einstein. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. (2010). Zeno’s paradoxes. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2010 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2010/entries/paradox-zeno/

  • Humphreys, P. (1985). Why propensities cannot be probabilities. Philosophical Review, 94(4), 557–570.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (1989). The chance of explanation. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Humphreys, P. (2004). Some considerations on conditional chances. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55(4), 667–680.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. (2014). Inscrutability and the opacity of natural selection and random genetic drift: Distinguishing epistemic and metaphysical aspects. Erkenntnis, this volume.

  • Jeffreys, H. (1961). Theory of probability, 3rd ed. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

  • Johnson, W. E. (1932). Probability: The relations of proposal to supposal; Probability: Axioms; Probability: The deductive and the inductive problems. Mind, 41(1–16), 281–296, 409–423.

  • Keller, J. B. (1986). The probability of heads. American Mathematical Monthly, 93(3), 191–197.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J. M. (1921). A treatise on probability. London: MacMillan & Co.

  • Kneale, W. (1949). Probability and induction. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kolmogorov, A. N. (1933/1950). Foundations of the theory of probability (N. Morrison, Trans.). New York: Chelsea Publishing.

  • Koopman, B. O. (1940). The axioms and algebra of intuitive probability. Annals of Mathematics, 42(2), 269–292.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Krips, H. (1989). A propensity interpretation of quantum probabilities. The Philosophical Quarterly, 39(156), 308–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kyburg, H. E. (1974). Propensities and probabilities. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 25(4), 358–375.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1967). Gambling with truth: An essay on induction and the aim of science. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1973). Review of Mellor’s The Matter of Chance. Philosophical Review, 82(4), 524–530.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Levi, I. (1977). Subjunctives, dispositions and chances. Synthese, 34(4), 423–455.

  • Levi, I. (1989). Possibility and Probability. Erkenntnis, 31(2–3), 365–386.

  • Lewis, D. (1970). How to define theoretical terms. Journal of Philosophy, 67(13), 427–446.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). Philosophical papers (Vol. 2). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loux, M. (Ed.). (1979). The possible and the actual. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maxwell, G., & Anderson, R. M, Jr (Eds.). (1975). Induction, probability and confirmation, Minnesota Studies in Philosophy of Science (Vol. 6). Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCurdy, C. (1996). Humphreys’s paradox and the interpretation of inverse conditional propensities. Synthese, 108(1), 105–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1969). Chance-I. In D. H. Mellor & J. Walting (Eds.), Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, supplementary volumes (Vol. 43, pp. 11–36).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1971). The matter of chance. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (1995). The facts of causation. London: Routledge.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D. H. (2005). Probability: A philosophical introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menzel, C. (2014a). Possible worlds. In Edward N. Zalta (Ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2014 Edition), forthcoming http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2014/entries/possible-worlds/

  • Menzel, C. (2014b). Actualism. In Edward N. Zalta (ed.) The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition) http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/actualism/

  • Miller, D. (1991). Single-case probabilities. Foundations of Physics, 21(12), 1501–1516.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (1994). Critical rationalism: A restatement and defence. La Salle, IL: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Miller, D. (2002). Propensities may satisfy Bayes’ theorem. Proceedings of the British Academy, 113, 111–116.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milne, P. (2005). Conditional probability, conditional events, and single-case propensities. In P. Hájek, L. Valdés-Villanueva & D. Westerståhl (Eds.), Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science, proceedings of the 12th international congress (pp. 315–331). London: King’s College Publications.

  • Mundy, B. (1986). On the general theory of meaningful representation. Synthese, 67(3), 391–437.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Padovani, F. (2011). Relativizing the relativized a priori: Reichenbach’s axioms of coordination divided. Synthese, 181(1), 41–62.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peirce, C. S. (1878/2011). On the doctrine of chances. In J. Buchler (Ed.), Philosophical writings of Peirce (2011, Chap. 12, Section I, pp. 157–164). New York: Dover.

  • Peirce, C. S. (1910/2011). A note on the doctrine of chances. In J. Buchler (Ed.), Philosophical writings of Peirce (2011, Chap. 12, Section II, pp. 164–173). New York: Dover.

  • Pincock, C. (2004). A new perspective on the problem of applying mathematics. Philosophia Mathematica, 12(2), 135–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2011). On Batterman’s “On the explanatory role of mathematics in empirical science”. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 62(1), 211–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pincock, C. (2012). Mathematics and scientific representation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A. (1976). Actualism and possible worlds. Theoria, 42(1–3), 139–160. Reprinted in Loux (1979), 253–273.

  • Poincare, H. (1902/1952). Science and hypothesis (W. J. Greenstreet, Trans.). New York: Dover.

  • Popper, K. R. (1934/1959b). The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.

  • Popper, K. R. (1957). The propensity interpretation of the calculus of probability, and quantum theory. In S. Körner (Ed.), Observation and interpretation in the philosophy of physics (pp. 65–70). New York: Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1959a). The propensity interpretation of probability. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 10(37), 25–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1967). Quantum mechanics without ‘the observer’. In M. Bunge (Ed.), Quantum theory and reality (pp. 7–44). New York: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1990). A world of propensities. Bristol: Thoemmes.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redhead, M. (1987). Incompleteness, nonlocality and realism: A prolegomenon to the philosophy of quantum mechanics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Redhead, M. (2001). Quests of a realist, Review of Stathis Psillos’ Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. Metascience, 10(3), 341–347.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. (1949). The theory of probability. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Réyni, A. (1970). Foundations of probability. San Francisco: Holden-Day.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosenthal, J. (2006). Karl Popper’s propensity interpretation of probability. In I. Jarvie, K. Milford, & D. Miller (Eds.), Karl Popper: A centenary assessment (Vol. III: Science, pp. 105–112). Aldershot: Ashgate.

  • Salmon, W. C. (1979). Propensity: A discussion review of Mellor’s The matter of chance. Erkenntnis, 14(2), 183–216.

  • Seidenfeld, T. (1978). Direct inference and inverse inference. Journal of Philosophy, 75(12), 709–730.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Seidnefeld, T. (1979). Philosophical problems of statistical inference: Learning from R. A. Fisher, Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (1968). A theory of conditionals. In N. Rescher (Ed.), Studies in logical theory (pp. 98–112). Oxford: Blackwell.

  • Stalnaker, R. C. (1976). Possible worlds. Nous, 10(1), 65–75.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suarez, M. (2013). Propensities and pragmatism. Journal of Philosophy, 110(2), 61–92.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Suarez, M. (2015). Deflationary representation, inference, and practice. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 49, 36–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Venn, J. (1866/1962). The logic of chance, 4th ed. Macmillan and Co. (Reprinted, New York, 1962).

  • von Mises, R. (1928/1957). Probability, statistics and truth, 2nd rev. English ed., London: George Allen & Unwin (1957).

  • Walsh, D. (2014). Variance, invariance and statistical explanation. Erkenntnis (this volume).

Download references

Acknowledgments

Parts of this paper were presented at the Current Projects Seminar, Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney, the Probability in Biology and Physics Workshop, IHPST, Paris, and the 41st Dubrovnik Philosophy of Science Conference, and I thank audiences at these venues for their helpful comments. For discussions and comments on earlier drafts of this paper, I am grateful to Ian Hacking and Alan Hájek and especially Isabelle Drouet, Delia Gavrus, Carl Hoefer, Philippe Huneman, Joel Katzav, Duncan Maclean and Noah Stemeroff. This research was supported by a SSHRC Insight Grant, a SSHRC Institutional Grant, a Victoria College Travel Grant and by the Centre for Time, Department of Philosophy, University of Sydney.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Joseph Berkovitz.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

About this article

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this article

Berkovitz, J. The Propensity Interpretation of Probability: A Re-evaluation. Erkenn 80 (Suppl 3), 629–711 (2015). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9716-8

Download citation

  • Received:

  • Accepted:

  • Published:

  • Issue Date:

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-014-9716-8

Navigation